Henry Johnstone Jr.

Henry Johnstone Jr. (1920–2000) was an American philosopher and rhetorician known especially for his notion of the "rhetorical wedge" and his re-evaluation of the ad hominem fallacy. He was Professor of Philosophy at Pennsylvania State University (1952–1984) and began studying Classics in the late 1970s.[1] He was the founder and longtime editor of the journal Philosophy and Rhetoric[2] and edited also the Journal of Speculative Philosophy.

Ad hominem

Ad hominem is Latin for “to the person.” According to Johnstone this means arguing from the perspective of the other person one is arguing with, not from one’s own perspective. This is not to be confused with the ad hominem fallacy. Ad hominem essentially allows an individual to critique from the inside out, making it easier to show the fallacies or contradictions in the other’s argument.3 Johnstone states that by using ad hominem “the clear mind can exploit the inconsistencies of the confused one. The force of this exploitation is to invite the latter to abandon ambiguity and incoherence.”4

Connection between philosophy and rhetoric

Early in his career, Johnstone viewed rhetoric as simply a means of deceiving the audience into believing a certain assertion made by the orator.5 He viewed philosophy in a more noble and truth-seeking light: “No philosopher worthy of the name would wish to secure assent to his position through techniques concealed from his audience.”6 He believed that arguments must be tested by the criticism of colleagues, not by concealing the truth. He later goes on to state that “the philosopher is obligated to tell the truth.” 7 A few years later writes that “rhetoric is relevant – highly relevant to philosophy.”8 Johnstone holds that if man is in fact a persuading and persuadable animal, not merely a communicating one, that not using rhetoric would be similar to treating man as a computer. He states that it could “plausibly be argued that communication is likewise a degenerate form of persuasion - a form in which we report not in order to incite people to action but merely for the sake of reporting.”9 His argument is that rhetoric is relevant to philosophy because rhetoric is a condition of human existence and that philosophy is a means by which one may be able to clarify that condition.10

Rhetoric as a wedge

Johnstone advanced and discussed the notion of rhetoric as “a wedge,” in the sense that it serves as a tool to open a gap between the input of data and its acceptance. The term is quite literal: “By ‘a wedge,’ I simply mean whatever introduces a gap.”11 Rhetoric serves as a wedge, because it helps individuals better understand, rationalize, and make judgments. Therefore, if individuals already knew everything, there would be no need for rhetoric as a means of interpreting data. This process proceeds by a bilateral exchange of responses. Although one may not respond to the orator, one does in his own mind and perhaps writes a critique.12 He makes a distinction between rhetoric as a wedge and rhetoric in a degenerate sense in the form of a command or threat. Once rhetoric degenerates to the level of commands or threats, it is no longer bilateral but unilateral, no longer making it a wedge by which one can interpret data.13 Prior to his death, Johnstone, along with Mari Lee Mifsud, attempted to “supplement the notion of rhetoric as a ‘wedge’ by suggesting the ways in which it is, and also must be, a ‘bridge’.”14 They state that rhetoric serves as a wedge in deliberative and forensic speech, but not in epideictic. Mentioning Aristotle’s advice that when the audience and speaker are already aligned in terms of a particular consciousness, the speaker need only to amplify and celebrate this consciousness, they conclude that “While this celebration is not a wedge, since it calls attention to nothing the audience did not already believe, it is a bridge.”15

Impact

Johnstone’s discussion of rhetorical and dialectical argument was viewed as being highly original, and at odds with the prevailing logical empiricism of the time.16 Scholars in both the fields of Philosophy and Rhetoric attribute Johnstone for significant advances in argumentation: “Johnstone's focus on the transaction of arguing had an immediate impact within the U.S. argumentation and debate community, directing attention to the normative aspects of controversy.”17 His extensive work on ad hominem argumentation provoked and challenged a series reexamination among philosophers. Many accredit him for adequately showing that ad hominem argumentation was quite typical surrounding philosophical writings, and had much broader use than previously thought.18

Notes

  1. Mifsud, Mari Lee (2000) "In Memoriam Henry W. Johnstone, Jr. 1920-2000." Informal Logic. Vol. 20, No. 2. 2000.
  2. Enos, R.J. (2000). "Always... An Epitaphios to Henry W. Johnstone, Jr." (1920-2000). Rhetoric Review, Vol. 19, nos. 1/2, Fall 2000.

3. Alfrid Snider, Henry Johnstone and Ad Hominem Argument, presented for lecture at the University of Vermont, (October 2009): http://vimeo.com.

4. Johnstone, Philosophy, Rhetoric, and Argumentation, 141.

5. Ibid., 141.

6. Henry Jr. Johnstone, “The Relevance of Rhetoric to Philosophy and of Philosophy to Rhetoric,” The Quarterly Journal of Speech 52, no. 1 (February 1966): 43. http://search.ebscohost.com.

7. Ibid., 45.

8. Ibid., 46.

9. Henry Jr. Johnstone, “Rhetoric as a Wedge: Reformulation,” Rhetoric Society Quarterly 20, no. 4 (Autumn 1990): 333. http://www.jstore.org.

10. Ibid., 336.

11. Ibid., 337.

12. Henry Jr. Johnstone, and Mari Lee Mifsud. “Wedge and Bridge: A Note on Rhetoric as Distinction and as Identification,” Rhetoric Society Quarterly 29, no. 2 (Spring 1999): 75. http://www.jstor.org.

13. Ibid., 76.

16. Douglas Walton, “Johnstone's View of Rhetorical and Dialectical Argument,” Informal Logic 21, no. 1 (2001): 1-9. http://www.phaenex.org.

17. Jean Goodwin, “Henry Johnstone Jr.’s Still-Unacknowledged Contributions to Contemporary Argumentation Theory,” Informal Logic 21, no.1 (2001): 42. http://www.phaenex.org.

18. Encyclopedia of Rhetoric, Thomas O. Sloane (Oxford, England: Oxford University Press, 2001).

External links

This article is issued from Wikipedia - version of the 10/25/2016. The text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share Alike but additional terms may apply for the media files.